I shall begin by defining civil disobedience
as a public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary
to law usually done with the aim of bringing about a change
in law or policies" (Rawls, 1971, p104).
"Civil disobedience may be defined as a principled,
purposeful and public disobedience of the law" (Goodwin,
1992, p319).
Historically, the doctrine of civil disobedience has variously
been advocated or employed by anarchists, anti-colonial nationalists,
and even disenchanted liberals. In this essay I shall look
primarily at the theories advanced to justify civil disobedience
by Rawls, Thoreau and Gandhi, and I shall briefly consider
some opposed to such actions. However, before considering
the justifications, and the resultant opposition, it is necessary
to clearly define ‘civil disobedience'.
As illustrated in the latter of the opening quotations, civil
disobedience can be defined threefold: principled (that is,
not selfish); purposeful, with the purpose of achieving a
change in the law; and public, due to the need for publicity.
An addition to this, according to Goodwin, the person who
undertakes a civilly disobedient act is bound to accept any
punishment that results from the act (Goodwin, 1992, p319).
For Rawls, civil disobedience is essentially non-violent when
used as tool for reform in a ‘nearly just society',
partly due to its public nature, but primarily as
"It expresses disobedience to law within the fidelity
of law, although it is at the outer limits thereof"
(Rawls, 1971, p106).
This notion of ‘fidelity to law' explains the willingness
to accept ensuing punishment, and also illustrates another
feature of civil disobedience, not that the system in general
(for the most part, a ‘nearly just' liberal democracy)
is at fault, merely one part of the system requires revision.
Indeed, the very term civil disobedience distinguishes it
from other, uncivil methods of disobedience, such as violence
or revolution.
Before examining the justifications of civil disobedience,
it is helpful to supplement the above definitions with some
contextual examples. Civil disobedience throughout history
has taken on various forms: from one man's refusal to pay
taxes to fund a war (Thoreau), to large groups of the population
refusing to pay the Poll Tax in Britain; from large sections
of a colonised nation refusing to obey British laws, yet accepting
the ensuing imprisonment (as led by Gandhi), to international
environmental pressure groups occupying oil rigs (Greenpeace).
A recent law passed in Britain, the Criminal Justice Act,
somewhat lends itself to civil disobedience, as it seen by
many to be a grave restriction on a great many liberties,
yet removes the very right to protest in many cases, a supposed
feature of all liberal democratic societies.
How then have scholars sought to justify the phenomenon
of civil disobedience? For Rawls, there are three points by
which one can justify civil disobedience, the first of which
is concerned with the particular wrong on which the civil
disobedience is focusing upon, for example legislation denying
basic rights to minorities, or non-egalitarian taxation laws.
The second point forwarded by Rawls is that reasonable recourse
to law, or other established method of appeal, has failed,
"The legal means of redress have proved to no avail"
(Rawls, 1971, p110), therefore civil disobedience is seen
as a last resort. The third condition relates to, and even
supersedes the other two, and although Rawls admits the first
two conditions are usually justification enough for civil
disobedience, this would not be the case if other minorities
also had similar claims to warrant civil disobedience, as
too much unrest may irreparably disrupt the existing liberal
democratic constitution (which to Rawls is nearly-just), and
demonstrates a lack of respect for the rule of law.
|